Who is responsible for overseeing research studies to ethical research standards are upheld?

Drawing on various national statements on the ethical conduct of research, the codes of ethics of professional associations and international agencies, and ethical guidelines in social research methods textbooks, this paper identifies current principles for ethical research involving humans and discusses their implications for impact assessment practice generally and social impact assessment specifically. The identified ethical principles include: respect for participants, informed consent, specific permission required for audio or video recording, voluntary participation and no coercion, participant right to withdraw, full disclosure of funding sources, no harm to participants, avoidance of undue intrusion, no use of deception, the presumption and preservation of anonymity, participant right to check and modify a transcript, confidentiality of personal matters, data protection, enabling participation, ethical governance, provision of grievance procedures, appropriateness of research methodology, and full reporting of methods. Topics such as a conflict of interest, moral hazard and duty of care are also considered. Also discussed are Indigenous peoples’ rights and their implications for ethical impact assessment processes.

Ethical issues and dilemmas arise in all forms of professional practice. Academic research in various disciplines, especially in the social sciences, also encounters ethical issues. While there has been an increasing codification of research ethics and professional practice ethics with the establishment of institutional ethics committees, views about the ethical implications of various research methods and practices vary across disciplines and in different cultural settings (Castellano 2004; Hoeyer et al. 2005). For example, much concern has been expressed by social scientists about the dominance of biomedical thinking in research ethics discussions (Israel & Hay 2006; Shore 2007; Dyer & Demeritt 2009; Amon et al. 2012). Therefore, with evolving practice in impact assessment practice generally and social impact assessment (SIA) practice especially (Vanclay 2002, 2003a, 2004, 2006, 2012; Esteves & Vanclay 2009; João et al. 2011; Vanclay & Esteves 2011; Esteves et al. 2012; Franks & Vanclay 2013), it is appropriate that ongoing reconsideration be given to the topic of ethical practice and to the kinds of ethical issues that can arise (Howitt 2005; Baines & Taylor 2011; Fuggle 2012). This is especially the case because ethical issues in professional practice rarely have simple right and wrong answers (Guillemin & Gillam 2004). An active awareness of the ethical issues likely to be encountered is important for reflexive and professional practice (Fisher 2008).

A hallmark of professionalism is an ongoing discussion of ethical issues within the professional group (Jowell 1986; Savan 1989; Wolpe 2006; Zandvoort 2008). Jennings (2003) considers that there are five general goals of ethics education for practising professionals:

  • Stimulating and broadening the moral imagination – practitioners need to learn about ethics, to understand ethical issues, to gain an empathy for people, and to interpret contexts in moral terms.

  • Recognizing ethical issues – practitioners need to be aware of when and how ethical issues occur.

  • Developing analytical skills – practitioners need to learn the vocabulary of ethics and moral argument, and to develop skills in analysing and addressing ethical situations.

  • Eliciting a sense of moral obligation and responsibility – practitioners need to develop an understanding of their personal obligations and responsibilities.

  • Coping with moral ambiguity – practitioners need to be aware of and able to cope with situations in which moral principles are in conflict with each other and/or where there is no obvious moral choice. Decisions in these cases should be based not on personal preference or vested interest, but on reasoned moral argument. The potential for moral ambiguity also means that individual practitioners need to be able to negotiate ethical judgements with others and be able to defend their decisions and actions on moral grounds.

This paper and its companion paper (Baines et al. 2013) seek to contribute to advancing these goals in the impact assessment field. While the companion paper discusses a range of ethical issues from the basis of the authors’ experiences of professional SIA practice, this first paper is relevant to all fields of impact assessment given that the principles of ethical human research are considered to apply to any research (i.e. data collection) process that involves human beings, whether humans are the subject of the research or only the providers of data. Thus, data collection for an (environmental) impact assessment that relies on asking people for opinions or information about biophysical issues would still normally be expected to comply with ethical research principles and procedures. The Australian national ethical research statement, for example, requires that its ethical principles be used in conjunction with any human research funded by any of the Australian government research funding agencies. Furthermore, it states that: ‘in addition, the National Statement sets national standards for use by any individual, institution or organisation conducting human research. This includes human research undertaken by governments, industry, private individuals, organisations, or networks of organisations’ (Australian Government 2007, p. 7). Social research ethics therefore potentially extend beyond SIA to all forms of impact assessment, and extend from academic to all organizational settings.

While academic research in many countries is clearly subject to the national generic and institution-specific requirements of the particular university in which the academic researcher resides, it is worth considering the extent to which research ethics might also apply outside the context of formal research institutions, to the professional practice settings in which most impact assessment professionals work. Although ethical research principles are sometimes used by institutions to protect the reputations of those institutions and to address risk considerations, nevertheless there is a legitimate, widely accepted, fundamental philosophical basis to the ethical principles. To that extent, these principles also apply to all practitioners, irrespective of their institutional setting. Thus, good professional practice would mean complying with ethical research as generally understood.

This paper (i.e. part I of a two-part paper) identifies the currently accepted ethical principles that apply to research involving humans and reflects briefly on the extent to which they apply to impact assessment. The companion paper (Baines et al. 2013) considers specifically how the ethical principles apply to SIA practice, drawing on the practice perspective of the authors. This first paper starts with a discussion of ethics and professional practice, before considering a range of codes of ethical research and identifying the major ethical principles in those codes. A concluding section provides some reflections relating to improving ethical conduct in impact assessment generally.

Ethics, or moral philosophy, is a branch of philosophy that seeks to address questions of morality. Morality refers to beliefs or standards about concepts like good and bad, right and wrong (Jennings 2003). When used as the basis for guiding individual and collective behaviour, ethics takes on a normative function, helping individuals consider how they should behave from a moral perspective, in other words, what they ought to do. Applied or professional ethics deals with ethical questions in many fields of professional practice, and many journals have been established, including: Bioethics; Journal of Business Ethics; Journal of Clinical Ethics; Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics; Journal of Medical Ethics; Nanoethics; and Science & Engineering Ethics. In addition, the mainstream journals of the professions frequently discuss ethical issues. Ethics apply to all aspects of personal and organizational practice and are therefore relevant to individuals, small firms, large corporations, government and non-government organizations, and to professions as a whole.

The application of ethics in a professional context often takes the form of a written code, document or agreement that stipulates morally acceptable behaviour by individuals within an organization or profession. In medicine and health research, for example, the Helsinki Declaration (World Medical Association 2000) is the defining statement. The American Anthropological Association (2012), American Evaluation Association (2004), Association of American Geographers (2009), American Planning Association (1992), American Psychology Association (2010), American Sociological Association (1999) and their equivalent organizations in many other countries of the world all have their various Codes of Ethics. Most professional associations in most countries of the world, including the International Association for Impact Assessment (International Association for Impact Assessment 2009), have some form of a code of ethics – as stated before, consideration of ethical concerns is a defining feature of being a profession. An excellent entry point for links to codes of ethics is the CODEX website established at the University of Uppsala with the support of the Swedish Research Council (http://www.codex.uu.se/en/etik9.shtml). Another entry point is the Council of European Social Science Data Archives (http://www.cessda.org/sharing/rights/4/).

Rossouw (2002) provides a useful discussion of the various features requiring attention when organizations develop a code of ethics, including consideration of purpose, process, form, content and implementation. He notes that some codes put more emphasis on promoting good practice while others emphasize the avoidance of malpractice. Some are aspirational in character, setting out ideal behaviours, while others are more directional, setting out actual behavioural requirements. Some ethical codes are more concerned with the implications of an individual’s behaviour for their professional colleagues within an organization, while others focus more on the importance of maintaining the confidence of external parties such as the public, the courts, the state, or key stakeholders. Rossouw argues that, if the purpose of a code is to establish agreement about shared values between members of an organization, then a consensus-seeking process is required.

In any jurisdiction, one can conceive of various intersecting sets of ethical codes and understandings. One sphere relates to the ethics of academic social science enquiry. Another sphere is associated with the ethics of professional practice where consultants make a living implementing social research methods in commercial contexts. Another relates to institutional guidelines of a government agency (the regulator or competent authority) or, in the few situations where they have them, the codes of conduct of the private sector commissioning party. Yet another sphere relates to the provision of expert advice in judicial or quasi-judicial situations where there are often specific legal requirements pertaining to the nature of evidence and disclosure of sources. Another sphere is the expectations of the affected population and/or of any significant subgroups within society at large. A final sphere might be the concerns of certain key stakeholder groups in society at large, including NGOs and watchdog groups, who might have particular ethical perspectives or expectations that need to be considered, not just about the process of assessment but also about the planned changes (or project) overall. What people consider to be ‘best practice’, ‘ethical’, ‘professional’ or even ‘acceptable’ practice usually depends on what standpoint they come from. This phenomenon is known as ‘framing’ (Kaufman & Smith 1999; Wynne 2001; Shmueli et al. 2006; Oughton & Bracken 2009).

Nevertheless, although these spheres do not necessarily share the same understandings of ethics or ethical obligations, some general and arguably universal principles can be inferred from moral and philosophical foundations. For example, one of the first national statements on research ethics to be implemented (although see Israel & Hay 2006 for a longer discussion on the origins of research ethics) was the Belmont Report (United States National Commission for Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research 1978), which arose in part in response to public outcry about various medical experiments, specifically the now notorious Tuskegee Syphilis Study which exploited, deceived and withheld medical treatment from rural black men in Alabama (Thomas & Quinn 1991; Shore 2007). The Belmont Report (United States National Commission for Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research 1978; also see Freed-Taylor 1994), which continues to be the basis of institutional ethics procedures in the USA, established that there are three overarching scientific norms that govern all research involving humans:

  • respect for persons – requiring both that the autonomy of persons is respected and that individuals with diminished autonomy are protected;

  • beneficence – by which they mean non-maleficence (i.e. an obligation to do no harm) as well as a need to maximize well-being; and

  • justice – ensuring reasonable, non-exploitative and carefully considered procedures with fair distribution of costs and benefits.

The Belmont Report differentiated between research and practice; however, more recent codes tend not to make this distinction. The Australian National Statement (Australian Government 2007), for example, has a lengthy discussion on the definition of ‘research’, making it clear that it should be understood in very broad terms. Nevertheless, Guillemin and Gillam (2004) make a case for ‘ethics in practice’ or micro-ethics, arguing that practitioners need assistance for dealing with what happens at specific individual encounters. The general view, however, is that ethical guidelines should not be prescriptive and that they will sometimes be contradictory. Rather than have specific rules for micro-situations, practitioners should be equipped with (and trained in) ethico-analytical skills to be able to make their own ethical decisions at the micro level and to be able to defend them at the macro level.

It is generally understood that professionals (and thus impact assessment practitioners) have ethical obligations to: society generally; employers, clients and/or funders; fellow colleagues, employees and in the case of academics to students; the professional community to which they belong and/or operate; and research participants and the communities to which they (the participants and arguably the professionals) belong (Marcuse 1976; Jowell 1986; Social Research Association (UK) 2003; Social Policy Association (UK) 2009).

The obligation to society was originally seen as being paramount, leading to a primary obligation ‘to protect the safety, health, property and welfare of the public’ (Holemans & Lodewyckx 1996, p. 22). The obligation to society requires impact assessment professionals to act with integrity, and to be committed to the fair and proper conduct of their research in terms of the collection of accurate data and the use of appropriate and valid analytical methods. They are expected to avoid real or perceived conflicts of interest (situations where they could personally benefit) and to be mindful of moral hazard (i.e. situations where the professional does not bear the consequences of any risks they take and may therefore be excessive in their suggestions or actions). They would be expected to restrict their activities to remain within their area of competence (Jamal & Bowie 1995; American Evaluation Association 2004). They have a duty of care, that is, ‘an obligation to take reasonable care to avoid causing foreseeable harm to another person or their property’ (Legal Aid Queensland 2012, online). They also need to ensure the provision of procedural and natural justice (Morrison-Saunders & Early 2008). The primary duty to society also means that there is an expectation that results of social research would be publicly available.

With the maturing of discussions about ethical professional practice in the different spheres mentioned above, a gradual change in the emphasis in the codes of ethics can be discerned. Earlier codes tended to focus on obligations to society and to the proper conduct of research, whereas newer codes tend to focus on obligations to research participants. Another way of expressing this change is that there has been a shift from normative ethics to procedural ethics (Kenny & Giacomini 2005). A specific example of this is in the Australian Government (1999, p. 11) National Statement, where Clause 1.4 states that ‘Each research protocol must be designed to ensure that respect for the dignity and well being of the participants takes precedence over the expected benefits to knowledge’, although this statement was not repeated in the 2007 version of the document. The 2012 version of the American Anthropological Association (2012, p. 9), however, clearly states ‘obligations to research participants are usually primary’.

Despite these varied contexts (spheres) discussed above, it is possible to distil a number of inter-related principles that are generally considered to be the basis of ethical research involving humans. This set of principles was identified by undertaking an in-depth literature review and a document analysis of key documents in the ethics in research field, specifically:

  • national and regional statements from governments or government agencies about research involving humans – for example, Australian Government (2007), AIATSIS (2011), the UK Economic and Social Research Council (2012), Institute for Employment Studies (2004), UK Civil Service (2005), United States National Commission for Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research (1978);

  • the ethical guidelines of various professional associations – for example, in addition to the American associations mentioned earlier, the Sociological Association of Aotearoa (New Zealand) (1990), The Australian Sociological Association (2003), the Social Research Association (UK) (2003), the Social Policy Association (UK) (2009), the (UK) Royal Anthropological Institute (2012), and the International Association for Impact Assessment (2009);

  • the ethical guidelines of various international agencies – for example, United Nations Educational Scientific and Cultural Organization (UNESCO) (1994), Tropenbos International (Persoon & Minter 2011) and the Convention on Biological Diversity (2004);

  • the discussion around research ethics as presented in social research methods textbooks – for example, Babbie (1989), Bulmer (1982, 2001), Hay (2010a, b) and Hennink et al. (2011); and

  • recent books and key journal articles specifically on professional ethics or ethics in research – for example, Gregory (2003), Guillemin & Gillam (2004), Haggerty (2004), Hoeyer et al. (2005), Richardson (2005), Israel & Hay (2006), Resnik (2008), Amon et al. (2012) and Hoekveld & Needham (2013).

The identified principles are described below. Not all sources mentioned above include all the principles described below, but rather the principles presented here represent an analytical summary of the principles implied or stated in the documents considered. In the language of qualitative research, the set of principles represents the themes that emerged from the analysis.

Although social scientists do not regard the principles as strict rules but rather as general principles to inform discussion and practice, institutional ethics committees have tended to interpret and implement them rigidly, resulting in resistance in various quarters (e.g. Adler & Adler 2002; Haggerty 2004; Israel & Hay 2006; Shore 2007; Dyer & Demeritt 2009).

Because of the wide use of social research methods in SIA, the ethical principles applying to social research might be considered as also applying to SIA practitioners. They also arguably apply to impact assessment practitioners who derive or access any form of data from people. We therefore present these principles in order to encourage discussion about ethical practice amongst all impact assessment practitioners.

The principles below are given in our words, but fairly reflect how they are understood in the social research field generally. Comments about their implications for SIA follow in the companion paper (Baines et al. 2013). While all principles potentially apply to SIA practice in general, there may be occasions when there is contradiction. In these situations, a practitioner would need to make a reasoned decision based on a balanced ethical judgement. The first two principles, respect for participants and informed consent, are the foundational principles from which all other principles cascade down. As the essence of ethical research, they are thus reflected in the other principles. Please note that the word ‘researcher’ is used in the principles, but this refers to anybody involved in a data-collection process and in the context of impact assessment therefore equates with practitioner.

  • Respect for participants – A researcher should always demonstrate respect in terms of all their interactions with participants including not judging them, not discrediting them, in ensuring that their views are faithfully recorded and given due consideration in the assessment process. Part of this respect is implied by the terminology of ‘participant’ (rather than ‘respondent’ or ‘subject’). An important dimension of this respect relates to ensuring the protection of persons with diminished autonomy, and those who are marginalized or vulnerable. Special recognition and procedures may also be required in the case of Indigenous peoples (see below).

  • Informed consent – Participation should be the voluntary choice of the participants and should be based on sufficient information and an adequate understanding of the research and the consequences of their participation. This implies that the researcher must disclose all relevant information and any possible risks of participation, especially any issues around what will happen to the data obtained. It is usually expected that informed consent be recorded in writing (as signed consent forms) and be producible by the researcher in the event of an audit up to several years after the research was completed. Israel and Hay (2006) provide an extensive discussion of what constitutes informed consent.

  • Specific permission required for audio- or video-recording – If the researcher intends to audiorecord (i.e. ‘tape’), videorecord (i.e. ‘film’) or photograph any participant, their specific approval for this must be given in advance (and may in fact be a legal requirement under the privacy legislation of most countries).

  • Voluntary participation and no coercion – As implied by the principle of informed consent, participation must be voluntary and not subject to any coercion or threat of harm for non-participation. Non-coercion is not taken to mean that there should not be payments for participation; however, any such payment should be commensurate with the amount of time and normal income expectations of the participants, and should not be excessive such that it would constitute a bribe or inappropriate inducement.

  • Right to withdraw – Consistent with the principle of voluntary participation, participants must know that they can withdraw at any time and have any of their data already recorded removed from the analysis where this is possible.

  • Full disclosure of funding sources – An implication of the principle of informed consent is that there must be full disclosure of the sources of funding for the research.

  • No harm to participants – It is fundamental that no harm must come to participants as a result of their participation in the research. This means not only that participants must not be exposed to pain or danger in the course of the research (such as in a psychological experiment or medical trial), but also that there must be no adverse consequences to a person as a result of their participation. This latter issue can be complicated. For example, a researcher cannot guarantee that an employer would not take action against an employee for their participation or for comments they might make, although such a risk should be addressed by ensuring the anonymity and/or confidentiality measures discussed below. At the very least, the researcher must do their utmost to protect participants from any harm, and to ensure under the principle of informed consent that the participant is fully appraised of all possible risks from participation. Sometimes, participation in social research will necessarily cause a participant to reflect on personal issues, bringing about emotional distress. Here the researcher’s obligation is to ensure that the research interaction does not finish until there is some resolution of the emotional distress that has arisen, and that there is recourse to follow-up assistance or counselling.

  • Avoidance of undue intrusion – Respect for participants means that there will be discussion only of those matters that are relevant to the issues under research and that enquiries should be confined to those issues. It implies a respect for the personal lives of participants and that researchers should be cognizant of what is personal and private.

  • No use of deception – The principle of respect for participants and professional integrity implies that the use of deception or covert methods should only be used under certain circumstances and only when approved by a duly appointed ethics committee.

  • Presumption and preservation of anonymity – There is an assumption of anonymity, that is, people participate in research on the presumption that they will be anonymous and that their anonymity will be protected, unless they have given permission to be named. Thus, there is a requirement for the expressed permission from participants for any use of the real names of people or where a person’s identity would be evident from the context (for example, the mayor or other public figure identified by the public role).

  • Right to check and modify a transcript – Where people are named or identifiable, those participants have the right to check how they are quoted and to make changes to a transcript and any draft publication that may be prepared to ensure they agree with the way they are recorded. Some codes (e.g. Australian Government 2007, clause 3.1.15) suggest that respect for participants means that all participants should be able to check their transcript for accuracy and completeness.

  • Confidentiality of personal matters – Respect for participants means that confidentiality (i.e. non-disclosure of information) should be accorded to all private or personal matters or views, or when any such undertaking is given. This means that there is a responsibility on the researcher to make judgements about what should be reported and what should not be publicly disclosed. The fact that something was revealed to the researcher does not automatically entitle the researcher to make it public. When information is entrusted to a researcher in confidence, such confidentiality must be protected.

  • Data protection – Because of the confidentiality of data, care must be taken to ensure that the data are stored securely and safe from unauthorized access. It is also expected that there be a stated timeline for safe disposal of the data. However, because of other institutional requirements that researchers be able to produce raw data in the event of an audit or complaint and to safeguard against fraud, typically this would be a number of years after completion of the project.

  • Enabling participation – Researchers have an ethical responsibility to ensure that all relevant individuals and groups are included in the research, and where they might ordinarily be excluded by reasons of language, access or cost to participate, that there be a genuine attempt to enable participation by providing appropriate means of access such as translation, transportation, or payments to offset the cost of attendance.

  • Ethical governance – For the proper functioning of ethical procedures it is necessary that there be a system of ethical governance in place. There needs to be a committee or other facility that can review research protocols prior to the research taking place, oversee and/or monitor research activities, provide advice to researchers and participants, and make judgements in relation to complaints.

  • Grievance procedure – Good ethical governance requires that participants have access to a grievance procedure and recourse to corrective action. The grievance procedure must be procedurally fair, and properly disclosed to participants.

  • Appropriateness of research methodology – Respect for participants as well as professional probity means that the research procedure must have reliability and validity. Participants give their time (whether free or paid) on the presumption that the research is legitimate, worthwhile and valid.

  • Full reporting of methods – Research methods and analytical procedures must be fully disclosed to: enable replication of the research by another researcher; enable peer review of the adequacy and ethicality of the methodology; and to encourage critical self-reflection on the limitations of the methodology and any implications for the results and conclusions.

These principles provide ethical guidance to researchers and practitioners and to the institutions in which they work. Rather than being implemented uncritically, the guidance is meant to encourage an understanding and critical reflection on ethical issues. It should be accepted that there will be circumstances that might obviate the rigid implementation of one or more of these principles, as discussed in the companion paper. However, all researchers and practitioners have an individual and collective responsibility to ensure ethical practice, with the team leader having overall responsibility and a specific role in ensuring compliance by all team members. Since ethical understandings will vary between individuals and across professional groups, there needs to be discussion of ethics in all team situations, especially given the interdisciplinary work contexts that typically apply in impact assessment.

The first principle listed above, respect for participants, would also imply respect for the individual and societal differences and beliefs of various peoples, and, for example, expecting that researchers/practitioners would not regard or treat everyone as being homogenous. A specific application of this principle that is very relevant to impact assessment relates to Indigenous peoples. Because of past serious cases of unethical research practice by various professions (Cochran et al. 2008), and because of the growing assertion of Indigenous peoples’ rights as manifested in, for example, the United Nations Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples (United Nations General Assembly 2007), various organizations, including the IAIA (Croal et al. 2012) have been developing codes of practice for research or other interactions involving Indigenous peoples (e.g. Castellano 2004; Convention on Biological Diversity 2004; Persoon & Minter 2011). One example of such a code was developed by the Australian Institute of Aboriginal and Torres Strait Islander Studies (AIATSIS 2011), with the key principles in that code being presented in Box 1.

  • Principle 1: Recognition of the diversity and uniqueness of peoples, as well as of individuals, is essential.

  • Principle 2: The rights of Indigenous peoples to self-determination must be recognized.

  • Principle 3: The rights of Indigenous peoples to their intangible heritage must be recognized.

  • Principle 4: Rights in the traditional knowledge and traditional cultural expressions of Indigenous peoples must be respected, protected and maintained.

  • Principle 5: Indigenous knowledge, practices and innovations must be respected, protected and maintained.

  • Principle 6: Consultation, negotiation and free, prior and informed consent are the foundations for research with or about Indigenous peoples.

  • Principle 7: Responsibility for consultation and negotiation is ongoing.

  • Principle 8: Consultation and negotiation should achieve mutual understanding about the proposed research.

  • Principle 9: Negotiation should result in a formal agreement for the conduct of a research project.

  • Principle 10: Indigenous people have the right to full participation appropriate to their skills and experiences in research projects and processes.

  • Principle 11: Indigenous people involved in research, or who may be affected by research, should benefit from, and not be disadvantaged by, the research project.

  • Principle 12: Research outcomes should include specific results that respond to the needs and interests of Indigenous people.

  • Principle 13: Plans should be agreed for managing use of, and access to, research results.

  • Principle 14: Research projects should include appropriate mechanisms and procedures for reporting on ethical aspects of the research and complying with these guidelines.

Although the AIATSIS and similar codes typically address the same issues as mentioned in the ethical research principles presented in this paper, in the AIATSIS, IAIA (Croal et al. 2012) and related codes there is an explicit mention of the wider rights of Indigenous peoples and the need for the researcher/practitioner to acknowledge and protect those rights. For example, the introduction to the AIATSIS (2011, p. 4) guidelines starts with the words:

Indigenous peoples have inherent rights, including the right to self-determination. The principles in these Guidelines … are founded on respect for their rights. These include rights to full and fair participation in any processes, projects and activities that impact on them, and the right to control and maintain their culture and heritage. AIATSIS considers that these principles are not only a matter of ethical research practice but of human rights.

It is clear that the data collection processes (i.e. research) being undertaken for impact assessments must not only respect international understandings of ethical social research, but must also comply with the expanding domain of human rights (Kemp & Vanclay 2013). The AIATSIS Principle 6 states that the principle of free, prior and informed consent (FPIC) should be applied even to research with or about Indigenous peoples. The same is the case with the code of conduct produced by the Netherlands-based development agency/NGO, Tropenbos International (Persoon & Minter 2011). Thus, FPIC is not just a concept pertaining to the development project for which an impact assessment is being done; the concept of FPIC also applies to the impact assessment process itself. When applied to research, ostensibly FPIC would in practice be no different to ‘informed consent’ as implied by the guidelines for ethical research; however, FPIC arguably has a more significant legal and international standing than ‘informed consent’. As FPIC, informed consent becomes elevated to a human rights discourse rather than being just a matter of ethical research practice.

The principles for research involving Indigenous peoples and the way they are put into effect are likely to have several consequences for researchers (and impact assessment professionals). It is important for practitioners to realize that Indigenous participation cannot be presumed or demanded. Indigenous peoples will be unlikely to accept the presumption that a researcher or practitioner has a right to do research or collect data. A convincing case as to why Indigenous peoples should participate will need to be made. The continued agreement of Indigenous peoples to participate in the research will probably depend on the practitioner being genuine, in treating the participants as equal partners in the process, and in the practitioner demonstrating meaningful engagement and reciprocity (AIATSIS 2011; Croal et al. 2012). This will mean that Indigenous peoples will want to negotiate about what research will be about, how it will be done, to what uses the results will be put, and how the data will be stored.

The commitment and adherence to ethical practice rely on the efforts of practitioners, as well as those of their client organizations and professional associations. Professional organizations such as the IAIA can promote and provide active support for ethical practice. There is a suite of measures that can be undertaken to support ethical practice at the individual and organizational level (extracted/modified from Rossouw 2002), including:

  • a participatory process for developing and reviewing a code of ethics for good practice;

  • a commitment to communicating the code of ethics, regularly and in varied ways so that it is reinforced amongst practitioners;

  • a commitment to ensuring that new practitioners become acquainted with the code;

  • the provision of opportunities for the open discussion of ethical dilemmas and case studies;

  • a commitment to the ongoing enforcement of the code by positive enforcement rewarding or acknowledging practitioners who behave in an exemplary fashion and by punishment of some kind for those who violate the code;

  • an organizational procedure for addressing code violations and providing necessary support to monitor compliance;

  • public commitment to the code, especially on the part of people who have high standing in the organization.

The ethical performance of an association can be considered by using the criteria above. For example, the IAIA can be evaluated against these criteria as follows:

  • Criterion 1 – the IAIA has developed and actively promotes its ethical statement (see International Association for Impact Assessment 2009) and Code of Conduct (see Box 2) amongst its members.

    As a self-ascribed professional member of the IAIA, the information and services that I provide must be of the highest quality and reliability. I consequently commit myself:

    • To conduct my professional activities with integrity, honesty, and free from any misrepresentation or deliberate bias.

    • To conduct my professional activities only in subject areas in which I have competence through, education, training or experience. I will engage, or participate with, other professionals in subject areas where I am less competent.

    • To take care that my professional activities promote sustainable and equitable actions as well as a holistic approach to impact assessment.

    • To check that all policies, plans, activities, or projects with which I am involved are consistent with all applicable laws, regulations, policies and guidelines.

    • To refuse to provide professional services whenever the professional is required to bias the analysis or omit or distort facts in order to arrive at a predetermined finding or result.

    • To disclose to employers and clients and in all written reports, any personal or financial interest that could reasonably raise concerns as to a possible conflict of interest.

    • To strive to continually improve my professional knowledge and skills and to stay current with new developments in impact assessment and my associated fields of competence.

    • To acknowledge the sources I have used in my analysis and the preparation of reports.

    • To accept that my name will be removed from the list of self-ascribed professional members of the IAIA should I be found to be in breach of this code by a disciplinary task-group constituted by the IAIA Board of Directors

  • Criterion 2 – the IAIA vigorously communicates the existence of the Code, and strongly encourages that practitioners endorse the Code by maintaining a register of signatories. It also has a status designation of ‘Sustaining Member’ given to the IAIA members who have signed the Code of Conduct and have four years or more of continuous membership.

  • Criterion 3 – the IAIA draws attention of new members to the code in various ways, including by making the Code prominent on the membership pages of the website.

  • Criterion 4 – the IAIA does provide opportunities for the open discussion of ethical dilemmas at its conferences, in its journal (such as in this and the companion paper) and newsletter, and in the online discussion forums that belong to each section of the IAIA;

  • Criterion 5 – Although the IAIA does have a suite of awards given annually, there is no evidence that the IAIA has demonstrated positive enforcement by having rewarded or acknowledged practitioners specifically for exemplary ethical behaviour or that there has been any punishment of those who may have violated the code.

  • Criterion 6 – the IAIA currently lacks a clear organizational procedure for addressing code violations and does not have the necessary support to monitor compliance.

  • Criterion 7 – the IAIA does facilitate public commitment to the code, including by people who have high standing, by maintaining a register of signatories to the Code.

In addition, to its Code of Conduct, the IAIA has developed a range of supporting information such as an ethical practice ‘fast tip’ (Fuggle 2012) and a range of best practice guidance documents which it makes available on its website (see http://www.iaia.org/publications-resources/downloadable-publications.aspx). It has also facilitated the publishing of a range of papers on the principles and/or best practice of impact assessment (e.g. Vanclay 2003a; Vanclay 2003b; Marshall et al. 2005; Canter & Ross 2010; Cave 2012), as well as various state-of-the-art papers (e.g. Adelle & Weiland 2012; Bond & Pope 2012; Bond et al. 2012; Esteves et al. 2012; Harris-Roxas et al. 2012; Morgan 2012; Fundingsland Tetlow & Hanusch 2012.

Comparing the IAIA’s Code of Conduct (Box 2) against the 18 principles for ethical research as presented in this paper reveals some shortcomings. The IAIA’s Code seems to be more typical of the earlier codes which, as discussed at the beginning of this paper, tended to focus on obligations to society and the proper conduct of research, rather than being akin to the newer codes, which tend to focus more on obligations to participants. It would be desirable for the IAIA’s Code to be revamped, increasing the emphasis on respect for affected peoples in the conduct of impact assessment and including requirements about ‘informed consent’ (from the research ethics discourse), and perhaps even ‘free, prior and informed consent’ (from the Indigenous rights discourse).

It is important to realize that ethical and professional practice is more than just having a Code of Conduct. All impact assessment practitioners need to be active in upholding and promoting ethical standards of professional practice through their own practice and by peer support. Most importantly, an ongoing dialogue is needed in the profession, a dialogue this paper and its companion paper seek to stimulate.

It is increasingly recognized that professionalism in all fields must be underpinned by ethical practice. Arguably, being ‘professional’ is defined by a commitment to and observance of ethical behaviour. However, like the various subfields of impact assessment, the fields of professional ethics and research ethics are also developing over time. The ethical expectations surrounding professional practice have become more exacting, covering the mechanics of undertaking data collection for an impact assessment (i.e. research), as well as the broader moral obligations and philosophical orientations in which impact assessment practice occurs.

A marked shift has occurred in institutional codes of ethics, with the primary obligation to society and the proper conduct of data collection becoming replaced by an increased focus on obligations to research participants. Respect for research participants (i.e. people) and ‘informed consent’ are now the primary ethical principles. Related to this primacy is that social research ethics are deemed to apply to all research that is about or with human beings. The term ‘research’ is now defined very broadly to involve any data collection activity as well as the creation of novel ideas. Thus data collection and other activities undertaken as part of impact assessments that involve people in any way whatsoever require that the ethical principles for research involving humans be considered.

The broadening of the field of research ethics also extends to the domains to which it applies. While institutional research ethics committees have typically been associated with universities or government-funded research institutions, there is an increasing social expectation that the ethical principles and procedures will be applied regardless of the setting of the research. Thus, private sector consultants engaged to undertake data collection for an impact assessment will increasingly be expected to comply with the same ethical principles as researchers in public sector agencies. Professional associations such as the IAIA need to play a key role in setting and enforcing these increasingly more exacting professional practice standards.

Best practice in impact assessment will essentially require full observance of the 18 principles documented in this paper: respect for participants, informed consent, specific permission required for audio or video recording, voluntary participation and no coercion, participant right to withdraw, full disclosure of funding sources, no harm to participants, avoidance of undue intrusion, no use of deception, the presumption and preservation of anonymity, participant right to check and modify a transcript, confidentiality of personal matters, data protection, enabling participation, ethical governance, provision of grievance procedures, appropriateness of research methodology and full reporting of methods.

The relatively recent rise in the recognition of human rights issues in impact assessment (Kemp & Vanclay 2013), the increasing acknowledgement of the rights of Indigenous peoples (United Nations General Assembly 2007; Croal et al. 2012), and specifically the concept of ‘free, prior and informed consent’ (Hanna & Vanclay 2013), will also influence the consideration of ethical issues that need to be considered in professional impact assessment practice in the future.

Through this paper and the companion paper, we hope to increase awareness of ethical considerations and to improve the practice of impact assessment.

This paper and its companion paper are a further development of a book chapter by James Baines and Nick Taylor published in Frank Vanclay & Ana Maria Esteves (eds) 2011 New Directions in Social Impact Assessment, Cheltenham: Edward Elgar. Comments were provided by Ana Maria Esteves, Philippe Hanna, Lucy McCombes, Angus Morrison-Saunders and students and staff of the Faculty of Spatial Sciences at the University of Groningen.

  • Adelle C, Weiland S. 2012. Policy assessment: the state of the art. Impact Assess Proj Appraisal. 30(1):2533. [Taylor & Francis Online], [Web of Science ®], [Google Scholar]
  • Adler PA, Adler P. 2002. Do university lawyers and the police define research values? In: van den Hoonaard WC, editor. Walking the tightrope: ethical issues for qualitative researchers. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. p. 3442. [Google Scholar]
  • AIATSIS. 2011. Guidelines for ethical research in Australian Indigenous studies. Canberra: Australian Institute of Aboriginal and Torres Strait Islander Studies [online]. Available from: http://www.aiatsis.gov.au/research/docs/ethics.pdf [accessed 16 August 2013]. [Google Scholar]
  • American Anthropological Association. 2012. Statement on ethics: principles of professional responsibilities. Arlington, VA: American Anthropological Association [online]. Available from: http://www.aaanet.org/profdev/ethics/upload/Statement-on-Ethics-Principles-of-Professional-Responsibility.pdf [accessed 21 July 2013]. [Google Scholar]
  • American Evaluation Association. 2004. Guiding Principles for Evaluators [online]. Available from: http://www.eval.org/p/cm/ld/fid = 51 [accessed 21 July 2013]. [Google Scholar]
  • American Planning Association. 1992. Ethical Principles in Planning [online]. Available from: http://www.planning.org/ethics/ethicalprinciples.htm [accessed 21 July 2013]. [Google Scholar]
  • American Psychology Association. 2010. Ethical Principles of Psychologists and Code of Conduct [online]. Available from: http://www.apa.org/ethics/code/principles.pdf [accessed 21 July 2013]. [Google Scholar]
  • American Sociological Association. 1999. Code of Ethics [online]. Available from: http://www.asanet.org/images/asa/docs/pdf/CodeofEthics.pdf [accessed 21 July 2013]. [Google Scholar]
  • Amon JJ, Baral SD, Beyrer C, Kass N. 2012. Human rights research and ethics review: protecting individuals or protecting the state? PLoS Med. 9(10):e1001325, doi:10.1371/journal.pmed.1001325. [Crossref], [PubMed], [Google Scholar]
  • Association of American Geographers. 2009. Statement on Professional Ethics [online]. Available from: http://www.aag.org/cs/about_aag/governance/statement_of_professional_ethics [accessed 21 July 2013]. [Google Scholar]
  • Australian Government. 1999. National statement on ethical conduct in research involving humans. Canberra: National Health and Medical Research Council. [Google Scholar]
  • Australian Government. 2007. National Statement on Ethical Conduct in Human Research, developed jointly by the National Health and Medical Research Council, the Australian Research Council, and the Australian Vice Chancellors Committee. [Google Scholar]
  • The Australian Sociological Association. 2003. The Australian Sociological Association: Code of Ethics [online]. Available from: http://www.tasa.org.au/about-tasa/ethical-guidelines/ [accessed 21 July 2013]. [Google Scholar]
  • Babbie E. 1989. The practice of social research. 5th ed.. Belmont CA: Wadsworth. [Google Scholar]
  • Baines J, Taylor CN. 2011. Ethical issues and dilemmas. In: Vanclay F, Esteves AM, editors. New directions in social impact assessment: conceptual and methodological advances. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar. p. 96113. [Crossref], [Google Scholar]
  • Baines J, Taylor CN, Vanclay F. 2013. Social impact assessment and ethical research principles: ethical professional practice in impact assessment Part II. Impact Assess Proj Appraisal. 31(4):254260. [Taylor & Francis Online], [Google Scholar]
  • Bond A, Morrison-Saunders A, Pope J. 2012. Sustainability assessment: the state of the art. Impact Assess Proj Appraisal. 30(1):5362. [Taylor & Francis Online], [Google Scholar]
  • Bond A, Pope J. 2012. The state of the art of impact assessment in 2012. Impact Assess Proj Appraisal. 30(1):14. [Taylor & Francis Online], [Web of Science ®], [Google Scholar]
  • Bulmer M, ed. 1982. Social research ethics. London: Macmillan. [Crossref], [Google Scholar]
  • Bulmer M. 2001. The ethics of social research. In: Gilbert N, editor. Researching social life. London: Sage. p. 4557. [Google Scholar]
  • Canter L, Ross B. 2010. State of practice of cumulative effects assessment and management: the good, the bad and the ugly. Impact Assess Proj Appraisal. 28(4):261268. [Taylor & Francis Online], [Google Scholar]
  • Castellano M. 2004. Ethics of Aboriginal research. J Aborig Health. 1(1):98114. [Google Scholar]
  • Cave B. 2012. Health impact assessment: principles and practice. Impact Assess Proj Appraisal. 30(4):302303. [Taylor & Francis Online], [Google Scholar]
  • Cochran PAL, Marshall CA, Garcia-Downing C, Kendall E, Cook D, McCubbin L, Gover RMS. 2008. Indigenous ways of knowing: implications for participatory research and community. Am J Public Health. 98(1):2227. [Crossref], [PubMed], [Web of Science ®], [Google Scholar]
  • CODEX (website supported by the Swedish Research Council). 2012. Professional Ethics Codes [online]. Available from: http://www.codex.uu.se/en/etik9.shtml [accessed 21 July 2013]. [Google Scholar]
  • Convention on Biological Diversity. 2004. Akwé: kon – voluntary guidelines for the conduct of cultural, environmental and social impact assessment regarding developments proposed to take place on, or which are likely to impact on, sacred sites and on lands and waters traditionally occupied or used by Indigenous and local communities. Montreal: Secretariat of the Convention on Biological Diversity [online]. Available from: https://www.cbd.int/doc/publications/akwe-brochure-en.pdf [accessed 21 July 2013]. [Google Scholar]
  • Croal P, Tetreault C, members of the IAIA IP Section. 2012. Respecting Indigenous peoples and traditional knowledge. Special Publication Series No. 9. Fargo, USA: International Association for Impact Assessment [online]. Available from: http://www.iaia.org/publicdocuments/special-publications/SP9%20Indigenous%20Peoples%20and%20Traditional%20Knowledge_web.pdf [accessed 7 September 2013]. [Google Scholar]
  • Dyer S, Demeritt D. 2009. Un-ethical review? Why it is wrong to apply the medical model of research governance to human geography. Prog Hum Geog. 33(1):4664. [Crossref], [Web of Science ®], [Google Scholar]
  • Economic and Social Research Council. 2012. ESRC framework for research ethics (FRE) 2010. Updated September 2012. Swindon UK: Economic and Social Research Council [online] Available from: http://www.esrc.ac.uk/about-esrc/information/research-ethics.aspx [accessed 21 July 2013]. [Google Scholar]
  • Esteves AM, Franks D, Vanclay F. 2012. Social impact assessment: the state of the art. Impact Assess Proj Appraisal. 30(1):3442. [Taylor & Francis Online], [Web of Science ®], [Google Scholar]
  • Esteves AM, Vanclay F. 2009. Social development needs analysis as a tool for SIA to guide corporate-community investment: applications in the minerals industry. Environ Impact Assess Rev. 29(2):137145. [Crossref], [Web of Science ®], [Google Scholar]
  • Fisher R. 2008. Anthropologists and social impact assessment: negotiating the ethical minefield1. Asia Pac J Anthropol. 9(3):231242. [Taylor & Francis Online], [Web of Science ®], [Google Scholar]
  • Franks DM, Vanclay F. 2013. Social impact management plans: innovation in corporate and public policy. Environ Impact Assess Rev. 43:4048. [Crossref], [Web of Science ®], [Google Scholar]
  • Freed-Taylor M. 1994. Ethical considerations in European cross-national research. Int Soc Sci J. 142:523532, [online]. Available from: http://www.unesco.org/most/ethissj.htm [accessed 21 July 2013]. [Google Scholar]
  • Fuggle R. 2012. Ethics. IAIA Fastip No. 2. Fargo: International Association for Impact Assessment [online]. Available from: http://www.iaia.org/publicdocuments/special-publications/fast-tips/Fastips_2%20Ethics.pdf [accessed 21 July 2013]. [Google Scholar]
  • Fundingsland Tetlow M, Hanusch M. 2012. Strategic environmental assessment: the state of the art. Impact Assess Proj Appraisal. 30(1):1524. [Taylor & Francis Online], [Google Scholar]
  • Gregory I. 2003. Ethics in research. London: Continuum. [Google Scholar]
  • Guillemin M, Gillam L. 2004. Ethics, reflexivity, and ‘ethically important moments’ in research. Qual Inq. 10(2):261280. [Crossref], [Web of Science ®], [Google Scholar]
  • Haggerty KD. 2004. Ethics creep: governing social science research in the name of ethics. Qual Sociol. 27(4):391414. [Crossref], [Google Scholar]
  • Hanna P, Vanclay F. 2013. Human rights, Indigenous peoples and the concept of free, prior and informed consent. Impact Assess Proj Appraisal. 31(2):146157. [Taylor & Francis Online], [Web of Science ®], [Google Scholar]
  • Harris-Roxas B, Viliani F, Bond A, Cave B, Divall M, Furu P, Harris P, Soeberg M, Wernham A, Winkler M. 2012. Health impact assessment: the state of the art. Impact Assess Proj Appraisal. 30(1):4352. [Taylor & Francis Online], [Web of Science ®], [Google Scholar]
  • Hay I. 2010a. Qualitative research methods in human geography. 3rd ed.. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  • Hay I. 2010b. Ethical practice in geographical research. In: Clifford N, French S, Valentine G, editors. Key methods in geography. 2nd ed.. London: Sage. p. 3548. [Google Scholar]
  • Hennink M, Hutter I, Bailey A. 2011. Qualitative research methods. London: Sage. [Google Scholar]
  • Hoekveld G, Needham B. 2013. Planning practice between ethics and the power game: making and applying an ethical code for planning agencies. Int J Urban Reg Res. 37(5):16381653. [Crossref], [Google Scholar]
  • Hoeyer K, Dahlager L, Lynöe N. 2005. Conflicting notions of research ethics: the mutually challenging traditions of social scientists and medical researchers. Soc Sci Med. 61(8):17411749. [Crossref], [PubMed], [Google Scholar]
  • Holemans D, Lodewyckx H. 1996. A case study of conflicting interests: Flemish engineers involved in environmental impact assessment. Sci Eng Ethics. 2(1):1724. [Crossref], [Google Scholar]
  • Howitt R. 2005. The importance of process in social impact assessment: ethics, methods and process for cross-cultural engagement. Ethics, Place Environ. 8(2):209221. [Taylor & Francis Online], [Google Scholar]
  • Institute for Employment Studies. 2004. The RESPECT Code of Practice [online]. Available from: http://www.respectproject.org/code/index.php [accessed 21 July 2013]. [Google Scholar]
  • International Association for Impact Assessment. 2009. Vision, Mission, Values, Professional Code of Conduct, and Ethical Responsibilities [online]. Available from: http://www.iaia.org/publicdocuments/miscdocs/Code-of-Ethics.pdf [accessed 7 September 2013]. [Google Scholar]
  • Israel M, Hay I. 2006. Research ethics for social scientists: between ethical conduct and regulatory compliance. London: Sage. [Crossref], [Google Scholar]
  • Jamal K, Bowie NE. 1995. Theoretical considerations for a meaningful code of professional ethics. J Bus Ethics. 14(9):703714. [Crossref], [Web of Science ®], [Google Scholar]
  • Jennings B, et al. 2003. Introduction: a strategy for discussing ethical issues in public health. In: Jennings B, editor. Ethics and public health: model curriculum. p. 112, [online]. Available from: www.asph.org/UserFiles/EthicsCurriculum.pdf [accessed 21 July 2013]. [Crossref], [Google Scholar]
  • João E, Vanclay F, den Broeder L. 2011. Emphasising enhancement in all forms of impact assessment: introduction to a special issue. Impact Assess Proj Appraisal. 29(3):170180. [Taylor & Francis Online], [Google Scholar]
  • Jowell R. 1986. The codification of statistical ethics. J Off Stat. 2(3):217253. [Google Scholar]
  • Kaufman S, Smith J. 1999. Framing and reframing in land use change conflicts. J Archit Plan Res. 16(2):164180. [Web of Science ®], [Google Scholar]
  • Kemp D, Vanclay F. 2013. Human rights and impact assessment: clarifying the connections in practice. Impact Assess Proj Appraisal. 31(2):8696. [Taylor & Francis Online], [Web of Science ®], [Google Scholar]
  • Kenny N, Giacomini M. 2005. Wanted: a new ethics field for health policy analysis. Health Care Analysis. 13(4):247260. [Crossref], [PubMed], [Web of Science ®], [Google Scholar]
  • Legal Aid Queensland. 2012. Dictionary of Legal Terms [online]. Available from: http://www.legalaid.qld.gov.au/legalinformation/Pages/Dictionary.aspx [accessed 21 July 2013]. [Google Scholar]
  • Marcuse P. 1976. Professional ethics and beyond: values in planning. J Am Inst Plann. 42(3):264274. [Taylor & Francis Online], [Web of Science ®], [Google Scholar]
  • Marshall R, Arts J, Morrison-Saunders A. 2005. International principles for best practice EIA follow-up. Impact Assess Proj Appraisal. 23(3):175181. [Taylor & Francis Online], [Google Scholar]
  • Morgan RK. 2012. Environmental impact assessment: the state of the art. Impact Assess Proj Appraisal. 30(1):514. [Taylor & Francis Online], [Web of Science ®], [Google Scholar]
  • Morrison-Saunders A, Early G. 2008. What is necessary to ensure natural justice in environmental impact assessment decision-making? Impact Assess Proj Appraisal. 26(1):2942. [Taylor & Francis Online], [Google Scholar]
  • Oughton E, Bracken L. 2009. Interdisciplinary research: framing and reframing. Area. 41(4):385394. [Crossref], [Web of Science ®], [Google Scholar]
  • Persoon G, Minter T. 2011. Code of conduct for working with Indigenous and local communities. Wageningen: Tropenbos International. [Google Scholar]
  • Resnik D. 2008. Environmental health research involving human subjects: ethical issues. Environ Health Insights. 2:2734. [Crossref], [Google Scholar]
  • Richardson T. 2005. Environmental assessment and planning theory: four short stories about power, multiple rationality, and ethics. Environ Impact Assess Rev. 25(4):341365. [Crossref], [Web of Science ®], [Google Scholar]
  • Rossouw D. 2002. Business ethics in Africa. 2nd ed.. Cape Town: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  • Royal Anthropological Institute. 2012. Ethical Policy [online] Available from: http://www.therai.org.uk/about-the-rai/governance/ethical-policy/ [accessed 21 July 2013]. [Google Scholar]
  • Savan B. 1989. Beyond professional ethics: issues and agendas. J Bus Ethics. 8(2-3):179185. [Crossref], [Google Scholar]
  • Shmueli D, Elliott M, Kaufman S. 2006. Frame changes and the management of intractable conflicts. Conflict Resol Q. 24(2):207218. [Crossref], [Google Scholar]
  • Shore N. 2007. Re-conceptualizing the Belmont report: a community-based participatory research perspective. J Community Practice. 14(4):526. [Taylor & Francis Online], [Google Scholar]
  • Social Policy Association (UKUnited Kingdom). 2009. Social Policy Association Guidelines on Research Ethics [online]. Available from: http://www.social-policy.org.uk/downloads/SPA_code_ethics_jan09.pdf [accessed 21 July 2013]. [Google Scholar]
  • Social Research Association (United Kingdom). 2003. Ethical Guidelines [online]. Available from: http://the-sra.org.uk/wp-content/uploads/ethics03.pdf [accessed 21 July 2013]. [Google Scholar]
  • Sociological Association of Aotearoa (New Zealand). 1990. Code of Ethics [online]. Available from: http://ethics.iit.edu/ecodes/node/3219 [accessed 21 July 2013]. [Google Scholar]
  • Thomas SCB, Quinn S. 1991. The Tuskegee syphilis study, 1932 to 1972: implications for HIV education and AIDS risk education programs in the black community. Am J Public Health. 81(11):14981505. [Crossref], [PubMed], [Web of Science ®], [Google Scholar]
  • UK Civil Service. 2005. Ethical assurance for social research in government. London: Civil Service Government Social Research Unit [online]. Available from: http://www.civilservice.gov.uk/wp-content/uploads/2011/09/ethics_guidance_tcm6-5782.pdf [accessed 21 July 2013]. [Google Scholar]
  • United Nations Educational Scientific and Cultural Organization (UNESCO). 1994. Ethical Guidelines for International Comparative Social Science Research in the Framework of MOST [online]. Available from: http://www.unesco.org/most/ethical.htm [accessed 21 July 2013]. [Google Scholar]
  • United Nations General Assembly. 2007. United Nations Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples. A/RES/61/295. New York (NY): UN General Assembly [online]. Available from: http://www.unhcr.org/refworld/docid/471355a82.html [accessed 16 August 2013]. [Google Scholar]
  • United States National Commission for Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research. 1978. The Belmont report: ethical principles and guidelines for the protection of human subjects of research. DHEW Publication No. (OS) 78-0012. Washington, DC: Government Printing Office [online]. Available from: http://www.hhs.gov/ohrp/humansubjects/guidance/belmont.html [accessed 21 July 2013]. [Google Scholar]
  • Vanclay F. 2002. Conceptualising social impacts. Environ Impact Assess Rev. 22(3):183211. [Crossref], [Google Scholar]
  • Vanclay F. 2003a. International principles for social impact assessment. Impact Assess Proj Appraisal. 21(1):512. [Taylor & Francis Online], [Google Scholar]
  • Vanclay F. 2003b. International principles for social impact assessment: their evolution. Impact Assess Proj Appraisal. 21(1):34. [Taylor & Francis Online], [Google Scholar]
  • Vanclay F. 2004. The triple bottom line and impact assessment: how do TBL, EIA, SIA, SEA and EMS relate to each other? J. Env. Assmt. Pol. Mgmt. 6(3):265288. [Crossref], [Google Scholar]
  • Vanclay F. 2006. Principles for social impact assessment: a critical comparison between the international and US documents. Environ Impact Assess Rev. 26(1):314. [Crossref], [Web of Science ®], [Google Scholar]
  • Vanclay F. 2012. The potential application of social impact assessment in integrated coastal zone management. Ocean Coast Manage. 68:149156. [Crossref], [Web of Science ®], [Google Scholar]
  • Vanclay F, Esteves AM. 2011. Current issues and trends in social impact assessment. In: Vanclay F, Esteves AM, editors. New directions in social impact assessment: conceptual and methodological advances. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar. p. 319. [Crossref], [Google Scholar]
  • Wolpe PR. 2006. Reasons scientists avoid thinking about ethics. Cell. 125(6):10231025. [Crossref], [PubMed], [Web of Science ®], [Google Scholar]
  • World Medical Association. 2000. World Medical Association Declaration of Helsinki Ethical Principles for Medical Research Involving Human Subjects. JAMA. 284(23):30433045. [Crossref], [PubMed], [Web of Science ®], [Google Scholar]
  • Wynne B. 2001. Creating public alienation: expert cultures of risk and ethics on GMOs. Sci Cult. 10(4):445481. [Taylor & Francis Online], [Google Scholar]
  • Zandvoort H. 2008. Preparing engineers for social responsibility. Euro J Eng Educ. 33(2):133140. [Taylor & Francis Online], [Google Scholar]